Pages in this section:
All sections:
Beware the transitivity trap
For want of a nail the shoe was lost,
For want of a shoe the horse was lost,
For want of a horse the rider was lost,
For want of a rider the battle war lost,
For want of a battle the kingdom was lost,
And all for the want of horseshoe nail.
(Thanks to Gary Goertz for remembering this one!)
The transitivity trap
Frog thinks: eating salad leads to health (less
scurvy), and health (general fitness) leads to better sprinting ability, therefore if I eat this yummy lettuce – AARGH!
One of the key features of causal maps is that you can draw
inferences, make deductions, from them. One of the most exciting is to
be able to trace causal influences down a chain of causal links. BUT,
when you are drawing conclusions from causal maps, beware of the
transitivity trap:
from
B → C
and
C → E
we can only conclude
B → E in the intersection of the contexts of 1 and 2
… and in general with any causal mapping, you’ll never be sure that
these two contexts do intersect. You actually have to look at each chain
and think about it, and hope you’ve been told all the relevant facts.
For example:
If
Source P [pig farmer]: I received cash grant compensation for pig diseases (G), so I had more cash (C)
and
Source W [wheat farmer]: I had more cash (C), so I bought more seeds (S)
can we deduce
G → C → H
and therefore
G → S
(cash grants for pig diseases lead to people buying more seeds)?
No, we can’t, because the first part only makes sense for pig farmers and the second part only makes sense for wheat farmers.
There are thousands of different kinds of transitivity trap. It isn’t just a problem across subgroups of people. It can apply for example in different time frames.
If
Child does well in year 13 (A) → Child has improved academic self-image (C)
and
Child has improved academic self-image (C) → Child does better in year 9 (D)
can we deduce
A → C → D
and therefore
A → D
(child doing well in year 13 leads to child doing well in year 9)?
Of course not - even though these claims might be true of the same
child. The problem arises as soon as we generalise one causal factor to
apply to different contexts. We have to do this, to make useful
knowledge. But there are always pitfalls too.
Not just a problem for causal mapping
This is also true, isn’t it, of any synthetic research / literature review?
And in statistics, knowing the effects from B → C and C → E means you
can calculate the indirect effect of B on E but not the direct effect.
You have to have additional data just for that. This is one source of
various so-called paradoxes in statistics.
Can we mitigate the trap with careful elicitation protocols?
Sometimes, we might know that all the information in one particular
chain came from the same source, and all this information was explicitly
given as a series of explanations of the factor which was initially in
focus. But even here, we have to be careful. We might have to ask again,
having reached the end of the chain, “did B really influence C which
influenced D which influenced E? Was this all part of the same
mechanism?” Are we sure we know exactly what we mean by this, and are we
sure that our respondents do too?
In any case, part of the point of causal mapping is the synthetic
surprises which we can discover by piecing together fragments of causal
information which were not necessarily provided in this way.
This is the situation every evaluator is in when piecing together
information from, say, experts for Phase 1 and experts for Phase 2. We
just always have to be aware of the transitivity trap.
Transitivity trap, or identity trap?
We can talk about the identity trap as more fundamental than the transitivity trap.
It comes down to saying, how can you be sure that the way in which this
factor is exemplified in one particular context is the same as the way
that this similar seeming factor is exemplified in a different context:
whether to use “the same” factor to code two different things.